I put my book reviews up on GoodReads -
www.GoodReads.com
- but, sometimes, I find that a book is not there, usually because the
publisher is small and specialist and has not entered into that great
marketing machine known as the Internet. In this case, there was no
entry but it seemed a shame not to comment.
Small
publishing enterprises should be encouraged especially if they are
experimental. That is not to stay that their works should not receive
the same level of rigorous criticism as bigger publishers but it is
better to be criticised and noticed than just be ignored.
Treadwells
is a bookshop and esoteric salon, with a well attended lecture series,
in London's Covent Garden
[now moved to Store Street]. It is not a publisher. However, in 2005 and
in 2006, it invited Stephen Alexander to give two sets of lectures,
first on sex and then on death, in an attempt to build a bridge between
the hard edge of continental philosophy and neo-paganism.
These
papers were edited and then published as The Treadwell's Papers
Volumes I and II (in fact, one paperback) earlier this year by Blind
Cupid Press.
The experiment is not a complete success as
we will see but it was an important and worthy attempt to bring some
intellectual rigour to the consideration of what is going on in the
world of the new religions and a chance for that world to hear from one
intellectual engaged deeply with the likes of Nietzsche and Foucault.
The
two sets of lectures must be treated separately because sexuality is
far more central (even when some practitioners go into a state of denial
about this) to most neo-pagan lives than death - although the idea of
natural cycles and (in some traditions) return is a powerful theme in
pagan thought.
However, we must make one criticism from
the beginning that applies to both books - Stephen Alexander's not
entirely explained obsession with DH Lawrence whose writings he
privileges in a way that they simply cannot bear.
DH
Lawrence is an important figure in English literary history and in
understanding English culture but he was not a philosopher. In fact, he
was often a hysteric - much like Bataille, another writer referred to by
Alexander, or Artaud - and his own thinking on sex and death is of
merely antiquarian interest, much like that of, say, HG Wells on
society.
This obsession with Lawrence and his works is a
barrier to understanding because, too often, especially in the second
volume on death, this paragon of highly intelligent male sexual hysteria
is taken not as an example (rightly in some places) but as a guide. He
is not. This detracts from the books.
Sex/Magic
The
Sex/Magic Volume is much superior to the succeeding one on death, in
part because Alexander really does contest with vigour some of the
wishy-washy aspects of neo-pagan mentality on the latter's ground.
He
is devastatingly right about the capture of a part of witchcraft by the
Jewish matriarchalism of Starhawk and the turning of sexuality into
that sort of tolerance that tut-tuts sexual beings into traditional
monogamy and right behaviour by the back door. Starhawk clearly fulfils
some social need but whatever she claims to be, she is not
truly 'paganus'.
I have decided not to waste time on the
distracting Laurentian arguments but what Alexander does with some
success is point to the tendency of paganism to owe too much to the
culture from which it is seeking to rebel, especially in regard to that
culture's dualism, especially male/female dualism.
The
history of the modern pagan revolt against Judaeo-Christianity is not a
simple break but a series of shuddering lurches where the advanced guard
leaves a substantial conservative force behind.
Crowley
now looks increasingly nineteenth century and Thelema reaches a
Typhonian high point in a man, Kenneth Grant, whose attitude to the
sexual is still secretive and dualist. Gardner too increasingly appears
to be carrying out in ritual the coded sexual tensions of the first half
of the twentieth century.
Alexander's service is a cruel
one here but a necessary one. Using Nietzsche as his type-philosopher (a
philosopher scarcely considered by the 'greats' of the neo-pagan
revolution though much earlier than they), he shows that a great deal of
popular neo-paganism is not as liberatory as it thinks it is - it has
revolted against one form of essentialism only to create new forms that
have not moved very far from Plato.
Of course,
existentialism is a damned hard school and it seems unfair to deprive
neo-pagans, in their own heartland, of solace in the essential. This is
an argument that applies equally to the Christian who may be embedded in
philosophical nonsense but who gains such solace that only the hardest
curmudgeon would deny their faith, hope and charity when they are not
persecuting others.
But if you ask a continental
philosopher into your inner sanctum, don't expect him to be anything
other than he is. The removal of the binary approach to constructing our
social reality has been revolutionary to the point that, now, anyone
who persists in binary thought is either a 'fool' (in fact, simply
uneducated) or a 'knave' (wilfully authoritarian or manipulative of the
dead weight of binary thinking at the heart of our current social
reality).
Good/evil, male/female, nature/nurture,
mind/body, black/white and so on have been embedded in our thinking as
much as top/down - that there is good, evil, male, female, mind, body
etcet. is unanswerable but that there is some clear dividing line
between categories that is not contingent and circumstantial is now very
contestable.
The tradition within neo-paganism
(though gnosticism too is fundamentally essentialist) that comes closest
to this thinking is the gnostic while neo-paganism still moves closer
towards continental philosophy than any other Western religion (the
Eastern religions actually influenced continental philosophy and are a
different kettle of fish).
Shorn of Lawrence, Alexander is
definitely worth reading and insightful on sex and the magical, relying
on Foucault as much as Nietzsche. On sex, he offers a short
intellectual boot camp for neo-pagans that they will either get or not
get and, if they get it, will move them sharply on from many traditional
reconstructionist forms.
There is not space here to
critique all six lectures but, after the introductory talk, Alexander
goes on to cover masturbatory fantasy (where he falls into his own
traditionalist trap in the end), the positive liberatory idea of 'cunt'
(where he provides a devastating account of the evil of female genital
mutilation that, in itself, rather knocks sideways any romantic view of
indigenous cultures), the meaning of anal sex, a subversive view of
nakedness in witchcraft (which is worth reading alongside Carr-Gomm's
recent review of nakedness in our culture) and an interesting view of
the masochistic and fetishistic aspects of ritual in Wicca.
I
do not always agree with his analyses. Alexander gets so bound up with
his argument that he comes out as a sort of moraliser for a particular
model of Foucauldian anarchy that subverts itself into a
surprising acceptance of a certain balance in favour of order.
Indeed,
he is often philosophically confused and the personal does seem to take
over ... he plays the magus to a vulnerable audience at such times,
less here than in the second book, in a way that I find just a tad
suspicious. Does he really believe all this or is he just playing?
However,
the manipulation and absurdities of his position are tolerable because
his insights are good. If you keep your wits about you and read him
without allowing the magician's misdirection and sleight of mind to
glamour you into futile shock or absurd acceptance, you will get a great
deal out of this series of lectures.
In summary, his
critique of modern neo-paganism stands up and is well-argued - even if
I, for one, see no reason why the kinder and more tolerant delusions of
these new religions should not continue to be encouraged as far more
beneficent than Judaeo-Christian miserabilism.
However, it
is this kindness and tolerance that, towards the end, Alexander seems
to want (or perhaps not want but be led by his logic) to undermine with
an attitude to the sexual that will appear not liberatory but
nihilistic. Some kind of implied psychic anger starts to appear that
obviates the claim to philosophy and this becomes more obvious in the
second volume.
Thanatology
This
second volume, on the other hand, was a disappointing series of
lectures not only because of the constant references to Lawrence (which
became simply tiresome after a while) but because it just did not work
philosophically - so much of it was blind assertion with very little
connection to specific neo-pagan concerns (quite unlike the 2005
series).
At the end of the 2005 Papers, Alexander seemed
to be particularly concerned to attack religious fascism, indeed the
fascistic mentality altogether, but in 2006, his ruminations on death
contain all the hysterical despair of the sort of late nineteenth
century or early twentieth century intellectual ripe for the blood lust
of ... yes, fascism.
Thanatology starts with a remarkably
black (to most people) vision of existence. Personally, I not only get
this but have written on it and have moved on from it but Alexander does
not seem to be able to move on at all.
His brilliant (at
this point) account of our place in Existence reminds one of Thomas
Ligotti's stories, which are one up in existential darkness from HP
Lovecraft, and the actual existential joy in the Nietzschean
'ubermensch' is often expressed as if he does not fully understand it
himself.
He sounds so black (not entirely without
philosophical justification) that you wonder whether it was an act of
cruelty to perpetrate this 'dark night of the soul' on a bunch of pagan
innocents at the first lecture. Still, it is smart stuff and the book
really only declines after this point.
Thanatology goes on
to cover Heidegger's concept of 'Da-Sein' (badly, I think, with the
same obsessive darkness of the introductory lecture), an unpersuasive
but genuinely stimulating discussion of the relationship between sex and
death (though he can sound a bit like Baudelaire after a particularly
rough night out), a view on suicide that goes beyond private rights
(where I stand) to such an espousal of the death instinct that even I
might have him removed from society for fear of his effect on the
temporarily disturbed young - and a section on human sacrifice which
takes him into the realm of nihilistic evil.
It is his
rather weak (in historical terms which seems to owe more to Frazer than
any serious reading of Aztec culture) lecture on sacrifice where he lost
me - and quite profoundly.
From his apparent liberatory
anti-fascist stance in Book I, his desire to show off as an intellectual
has had him turn topsy-turvy and, it would seem, at least implicitly
(pages 279-288), to espouse mass slaughter as a possible good in itself,
not the sacrifice of oneself but the sacrifice of others for some
grander narrative.
Bloody hell! Literally ... or is he
simply telling us what Nietzsche, Lawrence and Bataille have thought? It
is not entirely clear ...
Finally, he moves on to
Nietzsche's Death of God and a reinterpretation of Christ's Sacrifice
which sounds all very good as a literary exercise (which is how perhaps
we should see this Second Book) but which is undermined by a very simple
fact on which Heidegger would have put him right - er, Stephen, we
don't get up again when we die.
Neither do all those
slaughtered victims ... nor the temporarily young disturbed person who
kills themselves (though the case of Ellen West remains a corrective to
excessive determination to deny this private right). Sex is different
which is why he is on safer ground.
But even here,
Foucault's death from AIDS, as much as you may try and re-clothe it in
'choice' by a man who tried to kill himself and had masochistic
tendencies, the responsibility (unless you are a psychopath) for
another's life if a child is born and the fact that a woman does tend to
get dumped with the consequences, all suggest that the wilder shores of
what I would term sub-existentialist nihilism move very close to an
hysterical and disturbed attempt to acquire the attributes of
psychopathy (without being psychopathic) as a form of self-death.
Logically,
anyone who held many of the views in this second book for real as
opposed to literary effect, who did rather than talked - and most
intellectuals talk rather than do - would not only be dangerous to
social order (which might be a good thing) but could be dangerous to
their intimates and themselves (which is not).
Perhaps we
might call this second book a prime representation of the 'Heliogabalus
Complex' - the desire by troubled intellectuals who have no effect on
the world to create a fantastic vision of that world in which all values
are trans-valued not in order to make the world more true to itself
but a reflection of their own thoughts.
It is the ultimate
'the personal is the political'. Such gloomy intellectuals always
appear when things start spinning out of control and are always
attracted to the esoteric and the occult precisely because these latter
are often an 'absurd' attempt to re-make reality.
In fact,
this elitist intellectualism is very dangerous - it is neither truly
transhuman in the Nietzchean sense nor effective 'magic' (manipulation)
and is only a partial description of reality.
Neo-paganism
has arisen because of something greater than intellectual frustration
and narcissism. It is as 'false' as every other faith-based system but
it 'works' and does so under conditions of exceptional tolerance and
community. It is pragmatically good until the day that it gets 'power'
then it reverses its own polarity and becomes a problem. It is power,
not truth (and here we are with Foucault) which is at issue.
I
don't like Starhawk because she takes things too far towards the world
of power (over minds). I suspect that Gardnerian and Thelemite models
are already becoming sclerotic.
But the impulse to love
and build community from below is an important one, one that defies
Alexander's black vision of the universe, as not a truth (which it is
not) but as a reality (which it is).
The value of
continental philosophy lies in stripping away pretensions to truth. It
is counter-productive if it positions Non-Truth, paradoxically, as
Truth. We have not then progressed at all.
The fallacy of
Western intellectualism is thus to seek truth when there is no truth
that is not black - and to avoid dealing with realities which can never
be 'truth' but which are created by ourselves out of mind and matter in
different forms every second of every day in conjunction with billions
of other people as
useful to ourselves.
The
only Truth in this context is scientific and based on pragmatic
considerations of experiment and utility. The Western philosophical
project should be to give up seeking truth beyond science,
especially give up making the 'black' Truth into a reality as
meaningless as that of religion.
The art is to know the
darkness for what it is and to build pragmatic human-friendly realities
regardless of this - and just see what happens.
This is
exactly what real existentialism says - Nietzsche's myth of the Eternal
Return as a kick up the backside to build the reality you want
now,
while Heidegger's engagement with Da-Sein is a positive engagement with
reality without recourse to essentialist truths. You don't need a great
deal more than that.
So this is the paradox of
Alexander's work - he is still, despite everything, not merely trying to
find out the Truth as Non-Truth but seeking to drive it outwards to
others like any latter-day St. Augustine or Engels. He is in danger of
being to Foucault what these gentlemen were to Christ and Marx. He
should perhaps just ease up and go with the flow ...
But I
am glad he wrote these lectures. I am glad they were published. Despite
my criticisms, I think (if you are fairly strong-minded) you could
profit greatly be reading what he has to say. It may take you to the
edge but, if you do not do yourself in or leads legions to slaughter,
you should come out of it a stronger person.